As a matter of pedagogy, this contribution is meant to continue to provide a relatively easy entry point for many whose commitment to anti-capitalist action is not necessarily informed by theory. It's meant simply to whet an appetite for further layperson study and not to necessarily lobby for one perspective or another lest we get into the usual sectarian name-calling squabbles, denunciations, and party purges that occasionally devolve into anti-social behaviors. So "Warning, Warning Joan Robinson! Theory appears Below!"
So in this new lunar new year this diary will discuss how social media (as information searching) can help define the commodity in the LTV (labor theory of value). I have chosen a online cheat sheet summary to test an exam-worthy description and included it below the fold for you to check its veracity and perhaps discuss its critique (dialectically, even). The suggestion as always is that there are more ecumenical ways in which an anticapitalist discourse can be developed to support the continuing struggle.
Social media as commodity might be more than the sum of its crowds or interactive audiences as information commodities with more variable social capital construction (Poster) and some even claim that "Sorry, But Social Media Is Now A Commodity Skill", however mis-conceived.
Imagine that the production of fixed capital is conceived with cognitive processes as the means of production, that is to say, the brain is the factory and knowledge as a socially constructed industrial commodity(sic) might be considered as embodied past and present labor time, This formulation may not solve Marxian economics' transformation problem, but provides on the issue of networked economies a means by which problems of price and value can be less the orthodox controversy upon which a certain conceptual struggle has arisen in the theoretical community. This knowledge as congealed labor and as commodity stored as books or ebooks has of course associated prices and values controlled often by access (loan or purchase) yet as information has issues of fungibility and currency.
The US does not have the fastest network speeds
The most trivial example of this is the analog/digital database mailing list whose value is determined by exchange-value and use-value. For example in Amazon or for Comcast, these are network connectivity of credit/debit as well as user data (we're all paypals(sic)). Rented bandwidth or connection as a kind of constraint on access can be arbitrarily defined as channels or objects and the segmentation in the form of speed and status help to refine some of the issues that correlate to class and help explain the recent crisis over net neutrality. These more abstract rather than concrete relations as productive social relations are often more important than their carried content. And by extension, all of this activity displaces and diffuses and aggregates embodied labor as cognitive process far more interactively and spatially/temporally as social/cultural capital.
All of this brings to mind a beautiful diagram I came across in David Harvey’s sublime Companion to Marx’s Capital. There Harvey seeks to diagram the relations involved in those collectives that involve humans (it’s also important to recall that there are collectives that don’t involve humans at all). The powerful feature of Harvey’s diagram is that in mapping the interrelations between elements that belong to collectives in which humans participate, he expands that field of relations well beyond an obsessive focus on representation, the semiotic, the ideological, or the linguistic. The domain of representation is one element in these collectives, but only one. In addition representation we get nature, technology, modes of production, social relations, and the reproduction of daily life.
Yet another attractive feature of Harvey’s diagram is that the six domains he outlines here are more or less autonomous from one another. Often we get a picture of Marx where the base determines the superstructure. While the base certainly affords and constrains the superstructure, things are far more complex than this. Each of these domains interpenetrate yet develop at different rhythms and in different ways. Thus, for example, when you get electricity and the electric light in the domain of technology, this impacts modes of production, social relations, and representation. The working day becomes longer, you get new groupings of people afforded by the possibility of lighting at night, and the nature of representation undergoes shifts as a result of being able to read and write late into the evening. The point here is that change can come from many domains beyond the domain of representation. We cripple our thought if we focus on representation alone to the detriment of these other spheres. https://larvalsubjects.wordpress.com/...
This view of Harvey's is not at odds with the more orthodox conception of the dimensional commodity movement in Capital from production to consumption, from the two department model to the three department model of reproduction and its exponential increase in linkages, signalling a multiplicity of representations, which as digital data are commodities.
another Harvey diagram for the analysis of fixed capital from https://forthesakeofdeconstruction.wordpress.com/... gives us some of the limits and issues that relate to the heuristic examples from Capital that still ring true but require further explication especially on issues of production and reproduction when capital turns digital.
So, in a more concrete formulation of the prosaic social media means of reproduction, what would be the political economy analysis of Google? At one level it is the cultural / organic intellectual analysis of its role in forming social relations of production, circulation, and consumption as a "conduit" or network, but it is also its institutional position as a common-pool capital resource that makes it even more important since at one level it is a firm, but it is also itself a means of production as a search engine not owned by its users that ultimately accumulates capital, creates surplus value, and exploits society. OTOH, it can be instrumental in changing whole societies and promote radical social change if properly directed. But ultimately it is the speed, space, and time of money in the circuit of capital.
First a
preliminary algebraic introduction to the Circuit of Capital, noting that much Marxological blood has been spilled over these letters and their formulation in recent years.
First stage: The capitalist appears as a buyer on the commodity- and the labour-market; his Money is transformed into Commodities, or it goes through the circulation act M — C.
Second Stage: Productive consumption of the purchased commodities by the capitalist. He acts as a capitalist producer of commodities; his capital passes through the process of production. The result is a commodity of more value than that of the elements entering into its production.
Third Stage: The capitalist returns to the market as a seller; his commodities are turned into money; or they pass through the circulation act C — M.
Hence the formula for the circuit of money-capital is: M — C ... P ... C' — M', the dots indicating that the process of circulation is interrupted, and C' and M' designating C and M increased by surplus-value.
Karl Marx stressed that the globalization of production and circulation necessitates institutions that allow individuals to inform themselves on complex conditions. He said that “institutions emerge whereby each individual can acquire information about the activity of all others and attempt to adjust his own accordingly” and that these “interconnections” are enabled by “mails, telegraphs etc” (Marx 1857/58:161). Is this passage not the perfect description of the concept of the search engine? We can therefore say that Larry Page and Sergey Brin did not invent Google, but that rather the true inventor of the search engine and of Google was Karl Marx. But if Marx’s thinking is crucial for the concept of the search engine, shouldn’t we then think about the concept of a public search engine?
Another Google is possible, but this requires class struggle for and against Google in order to set free the humanistic (cognitive, communicative, co-operative) potentials of Google by overcoming its class relations.
More can be said on these matters outside of the usual blog length treatment, but it is a research area with heterodox implications that bridge many of the highly canonical commitments that anti-capitalists have made to their relatively autonomous affinity groupings.
Senility and dementia will make all that congealed cognitive labor so much cream of wheat so I'll leave the comments to sort out some of where the Marxological discussion should proceed, respecting other sectarian POVs with their own ideological preferences. After all "Mongo only pawn in game of life." especially where the choo-choo go.
Capital (Das Kapital)→Summary, Volume I: Parts I, II
Commodities, the Labor Theory of Value and Capital
Commodities are objects that satisfy human needs and wants. Commodities are the fundamental units of capitalism, a form of economy based on the intense accumulation of such objects. The basic criterion for assessing a commodity’s value is its essential usefulness, what it does in the way of satisfying need and wants. This usefulness is its use-value, a property intrinsic to the commodity. Commodities also possess an exchange-value, the relative value of a commodity in relation to other commodities in an exchange situation. Unlike use-value, exchange-value is not intrinsic to a commodity. Exchange-value allows one to determine what one commodity is worth in relation to another commodity, for example how many units of corn one might exchange for a given unit of linen. In a complex market, all sorts of different commodities, although satisfying different needs and wants, must be measurable in the same units, namely money.
Exchange-value as monetary value is what one means when one says a commodity has “value” in a market. Marx poses the question of where this value comes from. How is it that commodities with different use-values can be measurable in the same units? His answer is that universal measure for value, expressed in terms of money, corresponds to the amount of labor time that goes into the making of each commodity. Labor time is the only thing that all commodities with different use-values have in common and is thus the only criterion by which they are comparable in a situation of exchange. This is Marx’s labor theory of value. This theory implies that commodities have a social dimension because their exchange value is not intrinsic to them as objects but instead depends on the society’s entire division of labor and system of economic interdependence, in which different people produce different products for sale on a common market. Exchange-value allows this market to function. As an expression the amount of “congealed labor” in a given commodity, the value of that commodity, measured in monetary terms, always refers to the system of social and economic interdependence in which it is produced.
Marx elaborates on the relationship between a commodity’s value and its social dimension in a section on the “Fetishism of Commodities.” Commodities are meaningful in two ways, first and most obvious as objects of exchange with a certain a monetary value. The second, which is not so obvious and is in fact obscured by the first, is that commodities reflect not only the labor that went into making them but the social relations of production in which the labor was performed. This social aspect of commodities cannot express itself because in capitalist society the quality of a commodity is thought to emanate solely from its price, not from that which money expresses, namely social labor. The fact that people are moved to mistakenly reduce the quality of a commodity to money alone leads Marx to argue that modern capitalist society has invested the money-form with mystical or magical significance. Those who comment on the nature of economy, in particular bourgeois economists, reduce economics and the production and exchange of commodities to the behavior of money and in so doing always avoid looking at what commodities represent in social terms. In so doing, the bourgeoisie is conveniently able to ignore the fact that commodities emerge through an inherently exploitative system of wage labor.
Analysis
The Labor Theory of Value is not Marx’s invention, originating instead with classical economist David Ricardo, who developed a labor theory of price, which states that the prices of commodities represent the labor that went into making them. However, Marx’s labor theory of value differs from Ricardo’s and is given a drastically different significance within the larger context of his work. Marx’s focus on the nature of value is intended to show that the modern capitalist system of production and exchange is not what it seems. Although economic activity is apparently reducible to the behavior of money, to focus only on money is barely to scratch the surface. Production and exchange are social institutions, and their organization has social consequences. Capitalism, founded on a principle of private ownership, has the owners of the means of production (factories, raw materials) dependant on wage labor to create profits. Modern economists do not accept the Labor Theory of Value as an explanation of prices, but that is not really the sense in which Marx intended the theory to be used. Marx’s point is that the production of commodities is a social process, dependent on exploitation and giving rise to antagonistic relationships among classes, an idea that is not addressed at all in modern economics.
Summary, Volume 1: Parts II –V
Capital, Surplus Value, and Exploitation
Marx differentiates ordinary money from capital. In the simplest form of circulation of commodities, a commodity is transformed into money, which is then transformed back into a commodity as someone sells a commodity for money and then uses that money to buy a commodity they need. In this very basic market arrangement, people produce commodities so that they can obtain money to buy the commodities that they need. This dynamic naturally emerges in societies with a simple division of labor, in which different people specialize in the production of different commodities. Capitalism operates in accordance with different principles. Capitalists do not see money as a means of exchanging the commodities they produce for the commodities they need but as something to be sought after for its own sake. The capitalist starts with money, transforms it into commodities, then transforms those commodities into more money. Capital is money used to obtain more money. These two different arrangements are summed up respectively in the diagrams C-M-C and M-C-M (C = commodity; M = money). Capitalists are primarily interested in the accumulation of capital and not in the commodities themselves.
To increase their capital, capitalists rely on workers who put their labor power at the disposal of capitalists. Workers treat their labor power as a commodity and sell it to factory owners. The capitalist buys the workers’ labor power and puts the worker to use making products. The capitalist appropriates the product, since it does not belong to the worker, and sells it on the market. Capital accumulates through the creation of surplus-value. Since a commodity’s value equals the labor time congealed in it, this extra value can only come from the workers. In fact, says Marx, the capitalist forces the worker to work longer hours to generate this surplus value. The capitalist, to generate profits, must keep the working day at a certain length. Part of the day is spent generating value that keeps the workers fed and clothed, while the remainder is spent generating surplus value, which goes to the capitalist himself. This is the essence of exploitation.
The capitalist, who must submit his commodities to the exchange market at a competitive price, will buy as much labor power from the worker at the lowest price possible, which is no more than the cost of keeping the worker alive. Where neither laws exist to regulate this system nor any mechanism for collective bargaining, the capitalist is in a position to decide the terms of this relationship to the detriment of the worker. For example, in industrial England prior to legislation limiting the length of the working day, workers had no power and were forced to work long days in horrible conditions for wages that barely kept them fed. This struggle over the length of the working day is illustrative of the struggles in capitalist society generally. The exploitative relationship has capitalists trying to get as much from the worker as possible and the worker trying to limit the capitalist’s power to do so.
Analysis
Marx’s account of the exploitative relationship of capitalist to labor remains powerfully compelling and seems by many to be vindicated in history. Essentially, Marx argues that the mechanism of exploitation built into the capitalist economic system is the source of social antagonisms that will eventually lead to the dismantling of capitalism itself. In the early Hegelian writings, Marx looks to a notion of alienation, the estrangement of the worker from his humanity, to support the same prognosis. With the theory of exploitation and surplus value, he shifts away from philosophical language toward an economic frame of reference, though a common element, the idea that the capitalist social relations of production will lead to a destruction of the capitalist mode of production. The later formulation is more effective than the earlier, as it accompanies an analysis of actual historical events rather than purely speculative thought.
Writing in exile in England, Marx was able to view firsthand the workings of the world’s most advanced industrial economy. Scenes of textile laborers in industrial Manchester living in abject squalor and barely clinging to life, the poet William Blake’s evocative and disturbing images of “dark satanic mills,” all impressed on many the downside of growing production and prosperity that had become evident in England and throughout much of Europe. Marx tried to show that such poverty was a permanent feature of capitalism and in fact would grow worse as capitalism advanced. With no means of defense, the working class’s economic well-being is at the mercy of capitalists. But the capitalist, if he wishes to survive in a competitive market, cannot exercise mercy without endangering his enterprise. Classes grow out of this antagonistic relationship that exposes their bare economic interests. The bourgeoisie unite to defend their monopoly over workers using all the means at their disposal, including the state and even religion. While workers, through common association, gradually manage to unite to push back the capitalist. In England, the Parliament, through growing pressure of workers and their sympathetic advocates among the upper classes, finally decided to intervene in this exploitative relationship.